What is right and wrong for war robots?


Thomas Hellström

 

 

A Swedish version of this article is published in  Forskning & Framsteg No.5/6-2012

 

 

 

Description: http://bestgamewallpapers.com/files/mass-effect-3/atlas-war-robot_wide.jpg

Back Home

 

 

 

 

 

Recently, robotics researchers, computer scientists and cognitive scientists have started to collaborate with philosophers, lawyers, sociologists and anthropologists in the new field of robot ethics. The aim is to explore and formulate ethical principles that will be needed for the advanced robots of the future. We will for instance need to determine if and how service robots for the elderly should be designed and introduced as a replacement for human caretakers. If such robots become popular and desired, a distribution policy problem arises: who will have the right to use and be served by these expensive robots? When the robots are able to make complex decisions, they will have to be equipped with ethical principles so that they behave in a way we humans consider to be ethically correct.

 

Robot ethics is relevant especially for the tens of thousands of military robots that recently have been deployed around the world. Most of these robots are unarmed and remote controlled, and are used for surveillance and to defuse explosive devices. The most controversial military robots are the unmanned planes, the drones, which for nearly ten years have been used by, among others, U.S. armies in Iraq and Afghanistan. The drones are remotely controlled from control rooms often located in the Nevada desert, and the decision to fire the missiles are taken by soldiers safety sitting far away from the war zone. A common argument against the use of these drones is that operators easily can become emotionally numb and do not realize that the video game-like situation is really about life and death, even if their own lives are never at risk. Those who argue for the use of drones often start from the same fact but draw different conclusions. They argue that people who are not themselves threatened by their lives are less easy on the trigger than fighter pilots who, in a fraction of a second, must decide whether or not to attack as they fly by targets they see on the ground. By this way of arguing, unmanned aircrafts are preferable from a moral standpoint, since decisions on fire are taken by people who do not feel the need to shoot first and ask later in order to save themselves.

 

Ethical considerations regarding war are by no means a new phenomenon. Already the Old Testament stresses the need to minimize harm to civilians in a besieged city. Much later, international treaties and protocols were formulated. The Geneva Conventions deal with treatment of people in war, and the Hague Conventions define ethical principles for the use of different types of weapon systems. It is interesting to note that views on what is morally acceptable vary with time. The use of crossbows was banned by the pope in 1139, probably because they allowed killing from a distance, something that would be hardly criticized today. If you want to regulate the hell of war, it is often necessary to choose between two evils. It is notable that the human rights organization Human Rights Watch recommends that aerial bombing in populated areas should only be done with so-called smart bombs that are themselves navigating towards a predetermined goal. This is not because they like bombing with smart bombs, but because these bombs are considered to cause fewer civilian injuries. Currently there are very few guidelines for the use of robots in war, but it is highly likely that such will be included in future international conventions.

 

New ethical issues arise as robots become more and more autonomous (self-governing), and especially when they are given the power to decide if and when weapons are to be used. A small number of these military robots are already in operation. SGR-1, manufactured by the company Samsung, is used to monitor the border between South and North Korea, and can automatically detect and shoot people who are moving within the border areas. Should such robots be allowed at all? And if so: should they be equipped with moral principles that govern their actions? In such case, how should these principles be designed? To answer the latter question, one may study guidelines for the behavior of soldiers in wars, as described in the Geneva Conventions. The Discrimination Principle means that you may only aim for combatants and not civilians, and the Principle of Proportionality means that the expected civilian harm must be proportionate to the anticipated military benefits of a military operation. A human soldier who follows such principles is typically considered ethically correct. The same principles could also be used to construct ethical robots. A military robot that behaves like a well-behaved human soldier could then be regarded as ethically correct. While this serves as a good first approach, it does not lead us all the way since we are likely to require more of a robot soldier than of a human soldier. A human soldier can sometimes be excused for having shot first and asked later. Of course it is reasonable to require that a robot soldier risks its existence to a greater extent than its human counterparts.

 

However, today's robots are very far from the kind of artificial intelligence we see in movies like Terminator and Star Wars. Technical and scientific breakthroughs in several areas are required before a robot can analyze and understand what is happening in the environment, and then act to achieve its own stated objectives. A major technical challenge for robots like SGR-1 is to distinguish between civilians and combatants. Even the normal case is hard enough, and one can easily imagine various types of complications. To determine whether an armed boy dressed in civilian clothes should be treated as a combatant is a dilemma already for human soldier, and is certainly more difficult for a robot. Some researchers argue that the problems are so big and fundamentally difficult that they can never be resolved in a satisfactory manner, and that we therefore should stop development of all military robots. For the time being, the principle of limited morality (bounded morality) is often applied. It means that the robots are only used in situations where moral considerations are greatly simplified. SGR-1 is used in the fenced border areas where no human beings, whether civilian or military, are allowed. The Discrimination Principle then becomes much easier to follow.

 

Another new issue is related to moral responsibility: Can and should a robot be considered morally responsible for its actions? We can again compare how we view people in similar regards. According to a modern view, moral responsibility is the result of pragmatic norms in a society, and is simply a control mechanism that we invented in order to promote actions we consider good and suppress those we consider evil. Will the intelligent and autonomous robots of the future be assessed in a similar way as humans? The spontaneous answer to that question is usually No, arguing that robots only do what they have been programmed to do. The moral responsibility then lies entirely on those who develop, manufacture and use robots. Although this may be a reasonable conclusion for the robots that exist today, we may look at differently in the not too distant future. People are considered to be morally responsible in varying degrees. Young children are considered as not morally responsible for their actions, and responsibility grows gradually with age. Employees may, to some degree, blame the boss and thereby abdicate responsibility for their actions at work. Furthermore, we attribute already now moral responsibility to dead things. Companies (legal persons) can hold property and enter into contracts, and they can both be prosecuted and punished, and also sometimes accused of what we call immoral behavior. There are studies on how people accuse industrial robots for errors that occur during work. The amount of responsibility assigned depends on the robot’s autonomy - its degree of self-governing, or if you wish, intelligence. Future robots, military as well as civilian, will definitely become more autonomous, and they will also be able to learn from their experiences, just as humans do. Their behavior will depend not only on what the programmers inserted into the robot's computer at the time of construction, but to a large extent also on what the robot has experienced after leaving the factory. It is not unlikely that such a robot, to some extent, will be seen as morally responsible for its actions.

 

If and when it comes to imposing "punishment" on robots that misconduct, a new ethical problem occurs: how should people treat robots? As a free fantasy on the unpredictable future, let us imagine a scenario where a military robot runs amok and commits a war crime. A closer analysis of the robot's memory reveals that the reason for its behavior can be found in the robot's previous experiences, as it has repeatedly witnessed massacres of humans and robots that it had responsibility to protect. This fact is regarded as a mitigating factor by the court. The robot thereby escapes the harshest punishment, permanent shutdown, and will instead spend the rest of its life as robot cleaner in the basement of the city library. Whether this treatment can be regarded as ethically correct, and meaningful, or not remains to be seen.